+---------------------------------------------------------------------+ | The following material is reprinted *with permission* | | Copyright (c) 1988 The Foresight Institute. All rights reserved. | +---------------------------------------------------------------------+ | This material is based on and builds on the case made in the book | | "Engines of Creation" by K. Eric Drexler. | | It is reprinted with the additional permission of the author. | +---------------------------------------------------------------------+ The Problem of Nonsense in Nanotechnology K. Eric Drexler MIT Artificial Intelligence Laboratory (Visiting Scholar, Stanford University) bogosity (bo gos' i ty) n. 1. A false idea or concept; misconception. 2. Inaccuracy; opposite of veracity. [colloquial usage in artificial intelligence community; from bogus.] flake, n. -ky, -kiness. One who habitually generates, spreads, or believes flagrant bogosities. Nanotechnology--the field embracing mechanical and electronic systems built to atomic specifications--seems certain to suffer from an impressive infestation of nonsense. There is nothing novel about a technological field suffering from nonsense, but a variety of factors suggest that nanotechnology will be hit hard. The health of a field depends on the quality of judgments made within it, both of technical concepts and of individual competence. If concepts are sound and credibility requires competence, the field will be healthy; if bogus concepts prosper and credibility and competence come unhitched, the field will suffer. Maintaining the health of a field requires concern with the quality of these judgments. Trends in academic interest and media coverage suggest that nanotechnology will receive growing attention. This field subsumes several others, including much of molecular electronics and advanced biotechnology. Flakiness in this broad field will tend to reduce funding and to reduce the number and quality of workers. Similar (but lesser) effects seem likely to spill over into all fields that appear similar in the eyes of reporters, managers, and politicians. A consensus on sound ideas, however, will tend to have positive effects. If bogosities thrive, they will also tend to obscure facts, hampering foresight--and as I argue in Engines of Creation, foresight in this field may be of extraordinary importance. Our Problem: bogosity equals. . . Experience already suggests the problems we will face in the quality of the technical literature, of media coverage, and of word-of-mouth. In estimating the future magnitude of this problem, a simple model may be of use: In this model, the bogosity in a field equals the bogosity imported from related areas, plus the bogosity generated internally, minus the bogosity expelled or otherwise disposed of. bogosity imported. . . Nanotechnology is related to several other areas. For example, the scale of nanotechnology makes quantum effects important--sometimes. But quantum mechanics is a peculiar and often misunderstood subject; popularizations of it shade off into brands of mysticism distant from anything a physicist would recognize. The quantum domain thus holds ample bogosities waiting to be imported. Further, misunderstandings of quantum uncertainty can be used to make molecular machines seem either mysterious or unworkable. Nanomachines may be developed through protein engineering, and some nanomachines will resemble biological mechanisms. Thus, nanotechnology borders on biology, a field rich in emotional issues and misconceptions, some shading off into mystical views far from anything a biologist would recognize. Genetic engineering (an enabling technology for nanotechnology) has been the center of a remarkably confused debate. Misconceptions about evolution have already led a New York Times writer (in a review of Engines of Creation, 10 August 1986) to suggest that developing molecular circuits and the like may take billions of years--on grounds implicitly suggesting that human designers will be no more intelligent than cosmic rays. Some applications of nanotechnology border on brain science and artificial intelligence--and quite aside from real applications, many people think of brains when they hear of molecular computation, and some people (for some reason) think that molecular computers will lead automatically to machine intelligence. Nanotechnology seems ripe for invasion by ideas linked to bogus "explanations" of consciousness, rooted in bizarre physical phenomena rather than in complex information processing. Finally, nanotechnology has many dramatic uses that border on science fiction: the ability to build things atom by atom leads naturally to strong materials, to self-replicating machines, and to a wide variety of systems with impressive performance, including spacecraft. The vast literature of science fiction holds a wealth of appealing, plausible ideas that are often inconsistent with physics and sense. It, too, will provide ready-made bogosities to import. . . .plus bogosity generated. . . Nanotechnology will offer fertile ground for the generation of new bogosities. It includes ideas that sound wild, and these will suggest ideas that genuinely are wild. The wild-sounding ideas will attract flaky thinkers, drawn by whatever seems dramatic or unconventional. Further, imported bogosities will interbreed, yielding novel hybrids. Inspirations and nonsense imported from quantum mechanics, biology, brain science, and science fiction may lead to suggestions for creating quantum biomolecular consciousness for space robots, or bioevolutionary nanomachines for giant brains. We can expect to hear of a host of vague devices and implausible concepts. In the policy domain, misunderstandings of opportunities and dangers will be translated into misconceived policy prescriptions. Researchers can expect to face both irresponsible advocacy and irresponsible opposition, both eroding support for the field. . . . minus bogosity expelled All this would be little problem if normal mechanisms would maintain the quality of ideas. But will they? Consider some of the problems: People distinguish fact from fiction best when the subjects are visible and familiar--but this domain deals with unfamiliar, invisible entities. Few know enough quantum mechanics, chemistry, or molecular biology to reject bogosities in these fields. Even those with knowledge in one field may fall victim to nonsense in another. People think more clearly when they have no emotional stake in the subject--but nanotechnology raises issues of life-and-death consequence, issues that will likely become clouded by emotion. People reject bogosities more rapidly when these can be subjected to practical tests--but in nanotechnology, many ideas can only be tested with tools that won't be developed for years. Refereed journals operating in an established field can help communities maintain the quality of information--but, this field is new and interdisciplinary; it lacks both a refereed journal and an established critical community. In short, nanotechnology is a fertile field for nonsense, and is presently short of effective quality-control mechanisms. What Can be Done? What can we do to reduce damage caused by nonsense? When asked to judge a surprising idea that cuts across disciplinary boundaries, one may be forced to say "I don't know." This does little good, but does no harm. To declare "No one can know" would often be to discard the distinction between what is unachievable using present tools for design and fabrication and what is impossible under known physical law. This position is often false. Likewise, to declare that all wild-sounding ideas are false would itself be false, if history is any guide. These blanket declarations of ignorance or rejection would do actual harm: By being false, they would add to the bogosity problem. By failing to distinguish among ideas, they would blur the very distinctions that need to be made. These distinctions often can be made, even in an interdisciplinary context. In judging people and bodies of work, one can use stylistic consistency as a rule of thumb, and start by checking the statements in one's field. The mere presence of correct material means little: it proves only that the author can read and paraphrase standard works. In contrast, a pattern of clear-cut, major errors is important evidence: it shows a sloppy thinking style which may well flow through the author's work in many fields, from physics, to biology, to computation, to policy. A body of surprising but sound results may mean something, but in a new field lacking standard journals, it could merely represent plagiarism. More generally, one can watch for signs of intellectual care, such as the qualification of conclusions, the noting of open questions, the clear demarcation of speculation, and the presence of prior review. In judging wild-sounding theoretical work standards should be strict, not loose: to develop a discipline, we need discipline. Over time, these problems will lessen. Community judgment will play a growing role as the community itself grows and matures. Eventually, the field of nanotechnology will be like any other, full of controversy and disputes, but built on a broad base of shared judgments. +---------------------------------------------------------------------+ | Copyright (c) 1988 The Foresight Institute. All rights reserved. | | The Foresight Institute is a non-profit organization: Donations | | are tax-deductible in the United States as permitted by law. | | To receive the Update and Background publications in paper form, | | send a donation of twenty-five dollars or more to: | | The Foresight Institute, Department U | | P.O. Box 61058 | | Palo Alto, CA 94306 USA | +---------------------------------------------------------------------+